ROUSSEAU
AND COLERIDGE: ANOTHER LOOK AT CHRISTABEL.
Chris Rubinstein
(The Coleridge Bulletin New Series No 1, (Winter 1992-93) pp 9-14)
In this paper I refer to CHRISTABEL the poem as the poem and
to Christabel the character by name. The aim of this paper is to present the
claim for a significant interpretation of the poem as a polemic of Coleridge’s
versus Rousseauism. Rousseauism is an awkward word but is used e.g. by Richard
Holmes in his biography though curiously not indexed. Here the word is
convenient short-hand. The implications of the claim if justified are probably
sensational but I emphasise the claim is not one of exclusivity. The poem
remains conspicuously rich in its culture and sources.
It must be common ground that appraisals of the poem are
subject to one or more reservations about its status as a masterpiece.
Misgivings are variously expressed, exasperation is one harsh judgment, but for
this paper the countless details are not at issue. In my view the claim if
justified is a total repudiation of all misgivings.
The claim receives no support from any direct statement by
Coleridge, and none as far as I know from any commentator to date. A word about
Coleridge’s preface of 1816. I suggest it should be treated with great reserve
with its near bizarre denial of any allegation of plagiarism, and its
interesting but peripheral reference to metre. Like KUBLA KHAN and THE ANCIENT
MARINER the poem has an aura of reticence and furtiveness about its meaning but
with a wealth of potential explanation.
In this paper I first give attention to Rousseauism in
ROUSSEAUISM in
Evaluating Rousseauism I assume most of us will think
primarily of his well-known and highly controversial theories of society and
the human condition. These were publicised for the forty years beginning, say,
about twelve years before Coleridge’s birth. However, I emphasise there was not
only the intellectual impact, formidable as this was, but also there was
generated a huge passionate feeling for a new vision of humanity and society.
Though we may incline to see the theories as arid, Rousseau’s own presentation
of them, or many of them, was very emotional and in literary form. Thus the
assessment of Rousseau as a founder of Romanticism. His two outstanding literary
works, THE NEW HELOISE, a novel in letter form, and EMILE, simultaneously a
novel and a treatise on education, are highly charged with emotional appeal. Likewise
the famous CONFESSIONS.
Supplementing in
[10]
were common.
In the context of Coleridge the G.M. may have a twofold
importance. First, Coleridge presumably took from an early age an intense
interest in journalism, which was later to prove a partly rewarding profession.
Secondly, the Rev. John Coleridge, the poet’s father, headmaster of a grammar
school, contributed at least one letter at length, i.e. in 1757. [3] It was a
level-headed if dogmatic view of the antiquity of elephant bones found in
I very briefly refer to the academic side of Rousseauism. It
could be viewed as in succession to or in conflict with the philosophies of
Bacon,
Our great interest is Coleridge’s interest in Rousseauism.
Hazlitt in THE SPIRIT OF THE AGE [5] lists Rousseau among the authors whose
books Coleridge had studied - no details are given. Then Coleridge was to
describe himself as. having once been “an infidel,” referring to his formative
years at Christ’s Hospital. I take this to mean Rousseauism in that no other
source seems as eligible.
THE FALL OF ROBESPIERRE, a dramatic work, co-authors
Coleridge and Southey, dates from the late summer of 1794, Coleridge not yet 22
years old. This was the period when Wordsworth was most enthusiastic about the
I turn to some of Coleridge’s observations on the works of
Rousseau. These include the ambiguous comment that he does not particularly
admire Rousseau. Coleridge’s pithy and hostile assessment of Rousseau’s theory
of education, as set out in EMILE, may be highly relevant to an understanding
of Geraldine’s personality. Coleridge was speaking to his friend Thelwall: “Thelwall
thought it very unfair to influence a child’s mind by inculcating any opinions
before it should have come to years of discretion, and be able to choose for
itself. I showed him my garden, and told him it was my botanical garden. ‘How
so,’ said he, ‘it is covered with weeds.’ ‘Oh,’ I replied, ‘that is only
because it has not yet come to its age of discretion and choice. The weeds, you
see, have taken the liberty to grow, and I thought it unfair in me to prejudice
the soil towards roses and strawberries.” (TABLE TALK July 27,1830) In TABLE
TALK of July 8, 1830 is the fascinating anecdote which is given so much point
by a cross-reference to EMILE. [7] One may reasonably conjecture Coleridge’s
deep and persistent feeling about Rousseauism.
In 1817 Coleridge had in an essay compared Rousseau with
Luther for historical impact. In THE FRIEND (Vol 1,p.34) there is his
demolition of Rousseau’s political theory of the general will. I also mention
the distinctive lines from the poem “Behold! her bosom and half her side — are
lean and old and foul of hue” (one version of poem). In the CONFESSIONS there
is the outstanding episode where the young Rousseau in
[11]
One may be reasonably certain that
for some years Coleridge was profoundly and favourably impressed by
Rousseauism, not exclusively but emphatically nonetheless.
I turn to THE NEW HELOISE, first translated into English in
1761, and rely on the Edinburgh translation of 1794 — three volumes, 1141
pages. The GENTLEMAN’S MAGAZINE of 1761 wrote: “There has lately been published
in French by the celebrated M. Rousseau a work in six volumes in twelve
entitled THE NEW ELOISA as letters of two Lovers dwelling in a village at the
foot of the Alps in which the various subjects the most interesting, in private
life are treated in a masterly manner, and the story which is simple is
conducted with an air of truth and nature that is seldom to be met with in this
kind of writing”. The 1794 translation has a blurb of Rousseau’s:” If any young
girl should dare to read a single page of this, she is inevitably lost.” The
father of Julia, one of the two lovers, is the Baron d’Etange. Remarkably, the
family name is Vaud . [8] The Baron compares with Sir Leoline — “the
Baron rich”. Julia’s father is a retired army officer, an aristocratic and
haughty person who dotes on his daughter and refuses to permit a marriage of
Julia and her lover, St. Preux. Julia’s mother has procured from Julia her promise
to break with her lover. Shortly afterwards Julia’s mother dies leaving the
baron grief-stricken. the Baron is further grief-stricken when, at the end of
the book, Julia dies.
Before Julia’s death, St. Preux becomes the tutor of her
children, Julia’s husband having learned of his wife’s previous love affair and
having forgiven her. This husband is a much older, worthy, but unexciting
person. Julia plans a marriage between St. Preux and an intimate friend of her
now widowed. This venture fails. Voltaire commented on the book: “Never has a
whore preached more and never has a valet seducer of girls been more
philosophic.” [9]
The correspondence of the book includes letters of other
persons, and here I have given only a most rudimentary idea of its contents,
but I refer to a few more prominent features for the claim.
Julia and indeed Rousseau opens her heart on the topic of
children laughing and leaping about, feeling happy and free:” Who can engage a
father to trust the feelings of nature when he embraces his child.”[10]
Remember the conclusion of part 2 of the poem. Then Julia displays her
intellect on the topic of educating children. Julia, in defiance of Rousseau’s
own philosophy in the slightly later EMILE, insists on the need to pluck out
weeds from the environment which forms part of a child’s education.
The last sixty pages or so centre on Julia’s death. While
rescuing one of her children from drowning in a lake, she contracts a fatal
illness. She writes and is written about copiously on her deathbed. She is
inclined to a belief in tutelary spirits and recalls her mother in this
connection. She dies a devout Protestant about to enter Heaven.
Sometimes the letter writers in the book break into verse,
and Romantic love and passion are never far away. The book’s remarkable
romanticism is primarily a literary expression of, and secondly a powerful and
engaging argument for, Rousseauism.
Although the later book EMILE has a romantic content it has
a much more intellectual approach and commands more respect than HELOISE. The
greatness of EMILE as a book both of philosophy and fiction is beyond doubt. [11] In Coleridge’s day its reputation was no
less. It is reasonable to suppose he had read the book carefully, probably
years earlier than the composition of Part 1 of the poem.
EMILE relates to the growth to adulthood of Emile, virtually
an ideal male person in terms of Rousseauism, and ultimately after a prolonged
and virtuous courtship he and Sophie, an ideal girl, marry. They are of course
in love. The book ends with the birth of their first child, a son. Emile, even
in manhood, is impossibly closely tutored by a devoted Rousseau personally.
Emile’s parents have a diminished status. The book contains the theories and
accounts of practices of education for which Rousseau is himself responsible as
the boy’s tutor. Sophie’s parents are responsible for her. The superiority of
the male is assumed by Rousseau as natural. Sophie’s fondest pastime is
needlework.
The disciples of Rousseau looked on Emile as a new and superior sort of man. The fictitious Emile had Rousseau’s independence of mind and spirit, without Rousseau’s vices. That Coleridge would have been deeply impressed for some years cannot be seriously doubted. There are, I believe, correspondences
[12]
between the book and the poem on the
basis mainly of principles, intellectual principles.
Take the geographical setting of the book. Basically there
is a rural environment, not
Yet there are subtle distinctions. The castle has been and
no longer is a fortress. The guard dog is superannuated. the populace,
obviously producing a healthy agricultural surplus, is contented. There is no
threat to security, Geraldine excepted. The Church as such has only a secondary
influence. Bard Bracey is almost the sole member of the intelligentsia, and is
presumably Christabel’s tutor. The aesthetics of castle life are far from
derisory. The sacristan whose job it is to look after Church treasures has to
toll the bell! Here is an ironic comment on the failings of the Church. But
Christabel’s Christianity remains impressive.
In Rousseau’s book there is a classic at length in its own
right - the creed of the Savoyard vicar. This exposition motivated bigots to
call for the book’s censorship, and for Rousseau’s imprisonment. The Savoyard
vicar is dedicated to the well-being of his parishioners but the authenticity
of his faith is nil. He is a deist. Godhead is the prime mover. Even this tenet
is a result of a process of elimination. Christianity is pragmatism, virtually
only social control. No wonder the book was placed on the index and incurred
the wrath of some Protestants.
Rousseau does not testify to the existence of the
preternatural, whereas for Coleridge awareness of its presence may be essential
for faith. Tutelary spirits may be surmised basically intuitively, if at all,
and have to be distinguished from the fiction of the supernatural. Both
Coleridge and Rousseau are against superstition which leads one away from an
interpretation of the poem as centering on witchcraft, despite some
consideration of that sub-cultural tradition by Coleridge. Emile is entirely
practical and of course humane, but faith in the preternatural forms an
integral part of Christabel’s own identity.
Now for the apparent confrontation in the poem between good
and evil. In the book the essential goodness of Emile, Sophie and the tutor
Rousseau himself tells. In the poem the near saintliness of Christabel derives
from her obedience as a daughter, her religious faith and her place in feudal
society. She prays and worships and by implication in the poem is educated by
Bard Bracey. In the book there is no evil presence save for the threat of
intrusion by social influences hostile to human progress as seen by Rousseau.
In the poem Geraldine may be as vital as Satan in PARADISE LOST, but
significantly her role may also be seen as a manifestation of Rousseauism in
practice in the
In the Conclusion to Part 1 of the poem: “the blue sky bends over all”. It is a recognition of the persona as all alive and a repudiation of a solipsist interpretation of life, attractive as Bishop Berkeley’s philosophy was to Coleridge. Rousseau had had no doubts on that score and I quote from the book: “Is not the wicked my brother?” [13]
I summarise the claim in this way. Coleridge made a profound emotional investment in the poem. Its
[13]
exceptional meticulousness and
exquisiteness both of verse and content point to unusually intense and
sustained motivation. If Coleridge’s deep inner conflict over the validity or
invalidity of Rousseauism is postulated, as I believe it ought to be, then the
poem as his own catharsis or purging or even exorcism is absolutely
intelligible. One can imagine sensibly an inner drive. or compulsion to write
the poem: to evaluate Rousseauism conclusively in the dynamic process and
product of the poem.
The verse form gives the poem the edge over Rousseau’s
prose. The verse form more than compensates for Coleridge’s aversion to
physical warfare against the disciples of Rousseau, the Republicans of
revolutionary
The conclusion to Part 2 of the poem takes us further.
Coleridge regrets “ a World of sin” and its apparent consequences (“O sorrow
and shame should this be true”), an emotive and contrary attitude towards
Rousseauism. This is almost the end of the poem.
The refusal of Coleridge, if such it was, to admit, let
alone to publicise, the poem as his own polemic against Rousseauism is capable
of explanation.
(1) On principle, because no poet is under a duty to explain
his or her poem, and may legitimately feel an overwhelming disinclination to do
so.
(2) Until well past 1800 it would have been foolhardy to
have spread the view than Rousseau’s works were worthy of consideration, even
with an aim of refutation. The sophistication of any such disclosure by
Coleridge would foreseeably have been unacceptable.
(3) After the establishment of the Holy Alliance though the
true explanation would probably have been safe from the point of view of the
establishment, Coleridge by then had lost any motivation to reveal his past so
ruthlessly. However, opposition from radicals and the left could have been
highly embarrassing to Coleridge as he would have foreseen.
If objection be taken to the choice of Rousseau as a key
figure in preference to other eminent and controversial persons and themes,
Coleridge’s failing marital relationship for one example, I answer in terms of
magnitude and duration of impact: Rousseauism far outstrips anything else in
sight. Other influences certainly were of weight to Coleridge, but were not in
the same class for deep and sustained inspiration for poetry at length and in
depth, i.e. for Coleridge’s verse at its supreme - multidisciplinary, profound
and integrated.
I have tried to make a case for the poem CHRISTABEL as greater than hitherto supposed. However, I assess my own effort more as a first step than a thorough exploration, although I am confident it points towards the latter as feasible.
© Contributor
1992-2005
[1] See
e.g. Benedict Nicholson’s “Joseph Wright of
Gwen Raverat’s “Period Piece”,1952, p.154; Fuseli, Frederick Antal’s “Fuseli Studies”, 1956, p.15.
[2] N.B.
The index volume from years 1731-1786. I am indebted to
[3] Vol. xxxviii, p.299.
[4] See
[5] See chapter entitled “Mr. Coleridge”.
[6] EMILE (Everyman edition) pp.317-8.
[7] Ibid. p.268.
[8] See Besterman’s “Voltaire”, Longmans, 1969, p.425.
[9] See Besterman’s “Voltaire”, Longmans, 1969, p.425.
[10] Vol. 2, p.195 of 1794 edition in English cited.
[11] See introductions to Everyman edition supra 1911 and 1955 editions (pagination identical).
[12] Excerpt
from Disraeli’s speech at
“The Feudal System - it is all very well to talk of the barbarities of the feudal system, and to tell us that in those days when it flourished a great variety of gross and grotesque circumstances and great miseries occurred; but these were not the result of the feudal system; they were the result of the barbarism of the age. They existed not from the feudal system, but in spite of the feudal system. The principle of the feudal system, the principle which was practically operated upon, was the noblest principle, the grandest, the most magnificent and benevolent that was ever conceived by sage, or ever practised by patriot....”
[13] EMILE, supra, p.247.